
A History of Chinese Political Thought
© Institute of Confucian Philosophy and Culture, 2020
A History of Chinese Political Thought, by Youngmin Kim. Cambridge, UK and Malden, MA: Polity, 2018, x + 273 pages. $26.95. Paperback. ISBN 9780745652474.
Befitting the author’s global background, a Korean trained in the US writing on China, this introductory book not only makes an important first step in approaching Chinese political thought historically, but also contributes to ongoing methodological discussions in the discipline of intellectual history at a moment when it is reconfiguring itself while turning global.1 Benefitting from what has been addressed by previous reviewers, this review focuses on the methodological choices Professor Youngmin Kim made when tackling the formidable task of writing a history of Chinese political thought from Confucius to the present while remaining faithful to historicity. I first discuss where his approach figures in the two scholarly communities that are coming closer than ever but are yet to be joined together—sinologists with an interest in political thought and Western2 intellectual historians with an interest in China—and then propose a few ways in which we can build on Kim’s work and move forward.
Since the early twentieth century, there have been many histories of Chinese political thought, if few in English.3 Compared with them, this slim book is neither comprehensive in topical coverage nor indepth on any period. Not every reader will necessarily agree with Kim’s interpretation of selective texts or the main theme he chose for each dynastic cycle, either. The new ground Kim broke lies in having discarded two prevailing assumptions that have been driving such histories to date: nationalism and the idea that Chinese political thought can be reduced to a few essential features that persist throughout Chinese history. In Kim’s account, Chinese political thought does not have such essences, nor is there one “China.” Rather, Chinese identity—one of the five threads holding the book together—is shown to be constantly contested and in continual negotiation. Moreover, authoritarianism by no means defines Chinese political thought, which Kim shows to be a rich source from which interesting thinking resources can be drawn, like the metaphysical republic discussed in Chapter 6. Perhaps most importantly, while Kim makes it clear from the opening lines in the Preface that in writing this book, he is responding to rising interest in China among nonsinologists, he does not write in the language of John Rawls or under any other Western conceptual framework.4 Different from the vast and rapidly growing literature on Confucian political theory, like the voluminous works on Confucian democracy or Confucian perfectionism, Kim treats Chinese political thought on its own terms.
These make the book a starting point in a new approach to Chinese political thought that promises to make the subject more interesting to sinologists5 and more capable of standing up to rigorous scholarly scrutiny among historians of political thought globally speaking. Of course, the downside of challenging the reader’s expectations is that it may not immediately resonate with them. The patient reader with an open mind, however, shall be rewarded by gaining a sense of the internal dynamism and diversity of Chinese political thought, the main goal Kim aimed for in this preliminary step.
Other than helping to get the nonsinologist reader off to a good start, this book also made a timely contribution to the discipline of intellectual history, which in some circles consists mainly of history of political thought.6 Since especially 2010, partly in response to the crisis of humanities in a neoliberal world,7 two trends have been on the rise unabatedly: the return of the history of ideas (McMahon 2014) and global intellectual history (Moyn and Sartori 2013). Two sides of the same coin, both stem from a desire to free ideas from being contained (Gordon 2014, 35) by their historical worlds, the former in time, the latter in space.8 This made the contextual method most influentially articulated by Quentin Skinner (1969) and practiced, with variations under a family resemblance,9 by a number of historians of political thought affiliated to Cambridge University at one point or another, inconvenient. As a result, concerted criticism was launched on this commonly agreed methodology in the historical study of past intellectual life,10 while new approaches were being proposed and the very identity of intellectual history became open to redefinition.11 By now, as Antony Black (2019, 2) implied in his review of Kim’s book for Global Intellectual History, a journal debuting in 2016 amidst these developments, the discipline has entered a “post-Skinner, post-Pocock age.”12
Black is right to regard Kim’s book as having contributed to historians of Western political thought methodologically, but perhaps in less conspicuous ways. First, while covering a similar temporal span, Kim’s approach is qualitatively different from the neo-Lovejovian (Gordon 2014, 35)13 history of ideas advocated by scholars like Darrin McMahon (2006, 2014) and David Armitage (2012, 2017). Rather, this book was written with the contextual method throughout: Kim opens each chapter with a painstaking reconstruction of the context, sometimes devoting half of the chapter to it (like in Chapters 4, 5, and 6),14 before beginning to discuss the political thought in this period. Instead of tracing the genesis and metamorphosis of an idea over two thousand years, Kim treats a different theme in each chapter. Underlying this is an assumption that as times change, so do the questions. Like R. G. Collingwood, Kim does not think there are perennial questions across time or one idea running through Chinese history. As a matter of fact, Kim did not even take ideas as the subject matter of his book, but rather the “thinking agents” (p. 17).15 It is precisely with this agent-based approach that he was able to steer clear of stereotyping or essentializing Chinese political thought, thereby succeeding in presenting it as a living tradition that changes over time and has great complexity within each period. In so doing, Kim points toward an alternative, albeit perhaps much more demanding, way to do longue durée intellectual history.
Second, while Kim did not state it explicitly, he was also exploring writing global intellectual history—he opens the book by addressing rising interest in China amidst the ongoing global turn across Western academia and closes it by pondering over the larger issues raised by China’s rise as a global power to this globalized world. Moreover, going out of his way to make this book user-friendly to nonsinologists (p. x), he customized it for a global audience. And, with what Lowbna El Amine (2019, 3) called his “ecumenical knowledge,” he freely drew upon or otherwise engaged with Western material where relatable, juxtaposing the Chinese case side by side with the Western one. On the other hand, while foreign relations were given an important role in each period’s political formation and thereby political thought, Kim’s case studies in the nine main chapters were not about the global circulation of ideas or thought on the global but were firmly grounded in the local. In this way, that is, studying the local under a global lens in order for it to have greater global relevance, the book points toward an alternative way to do global intellectual history that adds a much-needed perspective from an arguably non- Western16 scholar working on non-Western material to the discussions on the tension between the local and the global. In its gist, Kim’s approach is strikingly similar to the one J. G. A. Pocock, whose methodological statements Kim invoked a number of times (e.g., pp. 15, 17–18, 186), recently put forward. Against the proposition that “‘the quest for the global’ entails a critique if not an abandonment of the concept of ‘context,’” in an article titled “On the Unglobality of Contexts: Cambridge Methods and the History of Political Thought,” Pocock argued for the necessity to continue studying the local as well as to “retain the use of the methods of preglobal historiography,” on the grounds that different language-worlds will continue to exist actively in a globalized world (Pocock 2019, 1, 7, and 10). While Pocock, an historian of Western political thought, can hardly avoid being suspected of sounding a conservative note with an apparent attempt to justify parochialism, Kim’s contextualized study of mainly premodern Chinese political thought for current global relevance has shown that the same method applies to a different language-world and that the local, if not yet connected to the global, should be studied on its own. On the one hand, the focus on the local does not undermine its global relevance. Rather, it seems to be Kim’s assumption that the deeply local is global, given human communality. On the other, studying the local under a global lens entails no small change: as can be seen from the Preface, it shaped how Kim conceptualized the research from the beginning and guided his decision on how to formulate the results. And, of course, one needs to be globally knowledgeable, as Kim has made the efforts to be so, to be able to juxtapose different local cases side by side.
Another methodological contribution Kim’s book made is on extending the temporal range for global intellectual history. In the Introduction to Global Intellectual History, a programmatic book for this new subdiscipline, the editors Samuel Moyn and Andrew Sartori kept invoking Joseph Levenson (1920–1969),17 the one and only intellectual historian of China to be found there (Moyn and Sartori 2013, 6). In Kim’s book, however, we find many scholars working on China’s intellectual past, but no Levenson. To a great extent, this discrepancy has something to do with the former’s focus on the “modern” period,18 or more precisely, the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. When reviewing this edited book, Sanjay Subrahmanyam (2015, 131) has pointed out that this “lack of chronological depth” does not help with redressing the problem of Euro-centrism that practitioners of this new type of intellectual history apparently take issue with. Pushing this one step further, one could say that restricting global intellectual history to the few centuries when Europe dominated global knowledge production risks being essentially an extension of Hegelian universal history. By contrast, except for a few pages in Chapter 10 and the foray in the Epilogue, Kim’s book almost exclusively deals with the centuries before the nineteenth, the supposed time when “globalization” began.19 Like the proponents of the “Global Middle Ages” (Holmes and Standen 2018), Kim, himself a scholar of middle period China,20 takes it as a given that one can study the premodern period from a global perspective.
Finally, as El Amine has noted, Kim did not just study philosophical works, but made ample, and good, use of literary and art pieces as well. For example, in Chapter 5, he used the “Tale of Oriole” to present mid-Tang mainstream thought as a contrast to the new ideas put forward by men like Han Yu 韓愈 (768–824); in Chapter 10, he used paintings to tap into the thinking of the Qing emperors on how to govern a multi-ethnic and multi-cultural empire. Worth noting also is Kim’s taking classical commentaries as sources of political thought (pp. 21–22, 129, 164ff, 184), an approach shared by some historians of Western political thought, like Sophie Smith (2018) and Anna Becker (2017) in their work on Aristotelian commentaries. Underlying Kim’s use of such diverse forms of material is a conception of the identity of intellectual history that is much broader than history of philosophy.21
Taken as a whole, the methodological choices Kim made in writing this book constitute interventions not just in approaching Chinese political thought more historically, but also in what intellectual history is and how to do it at a critical moment when it is undergoing profound and perhaps irreversible changes. His having produced a historically-grounded interpretation of the diverse sources in Chinese political thought by applying the contextual method onto Chinese material suggests that shared historical method could be a common ground on which trust can be built and comparisons made among scholars working on various local worlds. Having such a common ground helps intellectual history to be reconstituted as truly global in character while retaining some disciplinary unity. To historians of Western political thought, this is not “methodological nationalism”—“global” being a spatial attribute and contextualism a method, the former does not necessarily entail discarding the latter;22 to historians of Chinese political thought, this is not welcoming methodological imperialism—ultimately, what calls the shots is helpfulness in our getting right about the past. As Ian Hunter recently demonstrated, the contextual method has a long history in the West that began centuries before the few figures usually associated with the so-called “Cambridge School.” Even among them, much of Skinner’s methodological writings was but an updated formulation of what Collingwood wrote in The Idea of History (Skinner 2001).23 And, certainly, this is not the only method that helps in studying past intellectual life, as Kim’s application of many other methods in addition to it has shown. Regardless, as Kim admitted in the beginning (p. viii), the contribution this book made was still preliminary. To move forward, more work needs to done, such as in the following directions.
First, fill in temporal lacunae. For practical reasons, coming as we are to an age with such deeply entrenched specialization, it is hardly imaginable for any individual scholar to be able to thoroughly command the literature on such a long temporal span. While Kim deftly drew on Chinese, Japanese, Korean, and English secondary literature, and certainly the sparse notes and concise bibliography do not reflect all the voracious reading across area and disciplinary boundaries that went into his preparations, still, much of his account has to be built on the historical work that had been done by other scholars. As such, where he takes big leaps, like from the end of Eastern Han to the founding of Tang and from the end of Tang to Southern Song, it gives an indication of where original research is needed. In particular, more work needs to be done on Northern Song political thought. The three passages on Wang Anshi 王安石 (1021–1086) (pp. 119–120) certainly do not do justice to the rich political thinking going on in the long eleventh century, a watershed period in the history of Chinese political thought with no less diversity than the Warring States period.
Second, deepen the analysis and broaden the juxtaposition. For instance, when discussing the notion of the political (pp. 47–48), one would expect to see an engagement with Michael Freeden’s work (especially Freeden 2013), if not Hannah Arendt’s (1958) as well;24 when discussing the existence of a republican vision under a monarchy (p. 114), James Hankins’s work on republicanism being not always exclusively nonmonarchical could help reinforce Kim’s argument (Hankins 2010; 2019, chap. 3). More empirical evidence can be found to support this as well: as my dissertation shows, this monarchical republic actually first emerged in the mid-eleventh century, after Emperor Renzong 仁宗 (r. 1023–1063) fell dysfunctionally ill in 1056 and lasting till the capable Shenzong 神宗 (r. 1067–1085) took the throne in early 1067. The Southern Song one was continuing its spirit, only changing its grounding from the phenomenal world to the metaphysical.
Third, work out a theoretical formulation for the kind of glocal intellectual history Kim practiced in this book and more actively participate in methodological discussions going on among historians of Western political thought. After the 1960s, sinologists have not shown much interest in this regard and apparently the pressure to turn global is not as great on scholars working on China, given the inherent global nature of working on this area in the West. But as this review has shown, Kim’s methodological choices, some explicitly stated, some implicitly made, are very much part of a global conversation that can be greatly enriched with the addition of perspectives of scholars working on non-Western material.25 It is perhaps high time to bridge the gaps separating these scholarly communities.26
Fourth, explore alternative narrative units. While Kim’s critical choice of the dynastic cycle can be justified—each dynasty was founded on the basis of a different social, institutional, and international structure, which set the contours of political issues for thinkers to respond to—one wonders if the time may be ripe for analyzing long historical cycles across several dynasties, like early China from Western Zhou to Han, or middle period China from Tang to Ming.
Finally, if this book goes into reprint—I hope it will, which was one reason this review was written—a few textual errors can be corrected. For example, on pages 11 and 255, “Nathan Sivin” should be “Benjamin Elman.” For some references, it would perhaps help to give the date of their first editions, like Mark Bevir ([1999] 2002, 17), for easier common reference, especially given that these appear in the main body.
We have Youngmin Kim to thank for having brought back to life, through rigorous contextualization, a dynamic and diverse tradition of Chinese political thinking that can have global relevance while being locally reconstructed on its own terms. With this volume in place, and with the translated texts in the history of Chinese political thought to appear in the globalized Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought under the co-editorship of Kim’s classmate Hilde De Weerdt from 2020,27 there is reason to believe that Chinese political thought will have more to offer scholars working on various areas on this globe as we grapple with political issues the global community faces together.
Acknowledgments
The author wishes to thank Hilde De Weerdt for recommending her to contribute this review and Philip J. Ivanhoe for the invitation.
References
- Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
-
Armitage, David. 2012. “What’s the Big Idea? Intellectual History and the Longue Durée.” History of European Ideas 38.4: 493–507.
[https://doi.org/10.1080/01916599.2012.714635]
- Armitage, David. 2017. Civil Wars: A History in Ideas. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
- Armitage, David. 2020. “In Defense of Presentism.” In History and Human Flourishing, edited by Darrin M. McMahon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
-
Becker, Anna. 2017. “Gender in the History of Early Modern Political Thought.” Historical Journal 60.4: 843–863.
[https://doi.org/10.1017/S0018246X17000061]
-
Bell, Duncan. 2013. “Making and Taking Worlds.” In Global Intellectual History, edited by Samuel Moyn and Andrew Sartori, 254–279. New York: Columbia University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.7312/moyn16048-011]
- Bevir, Mark. [1999] 2002. The Logic of the History of Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
-
Black, Antony. 2019. “Review of [A] History of Chinese Political Thought, by Youngmin Kim, Cambridge: Polity, 2018.” Global Intellectual History. (accessed February 15, 2020).
[https://doi.org/10.1080/23801883.2019.1573495]
- Bol, Peter K. 2013. “Words and Ideas—Methodological Contexts for China’s Intellectual History.” In Jinshi Zhongguozhi bianyu bubian 近世中國之變與不變 (Changes and What Has Not Changed in Modern China), 287–336. Taibei: Academia sinica.
- DeBlasi, Anthony. 2002. Reform in the Balance: The Defense of Literary Culture in Mid-Tang China. SUNY Series in Chinese Philosophy and Culture. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
- El Amine, Lowbna. 2019. “Review of A History of Chinese Political Thought, by Youngmin Kim, Cambridge: Polity, 2018.” H-Ideas, H-Net Reviews, February. http://www.h-net.org/reviews/showrev.php?id=53767, (accessed February 15, 2020).
-
Forrester, Katrina. 2019. In the Shadow of Justice: Postwar Liberalism and the Remaking of Political Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.1515/9780691189420]
-
Freeden, Michael. 2013. The Political Theory of Political Thinking: The Anatomy of a Practice. Paperback. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199568031.001.0001]
-
Gordon, Peter. 2014. “Contextualism and Criticism in the History of Ideas.” In Rethinking Modern European Intellectual History, edited by Darrin M. McMahon and Samuel Moyn, 32–55. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199769230.003.0002]
-
Goto-Jones, Christopher, ed. 2008. Re-Politicising the Kyoto School as Philosophy. London and New York: Routledge.
[https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203099322]
-
Hankins, James. 2010. “Exclusivist Republicanism and the Non-Monarchical Republic.” Political Theory 38.4: 452–482.
[https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591710366369]
-
Hankins, James. 2019. Virtue Politics: Soulcraft and Statecraft in Renaissance Italy. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.4159/9780674242517]
- Hansen, Valerie. 2020. The Year 1000: When Explorers Connected the World— and Globalization Began. New York: Scribner.
-
Holmes, Catherine, and Standen Naomi. 2018. “Introduction: Towards a Global Middle Ages.” Past and Present 238 (Supplement 13, The Global Middle Ages): 1–44.
[https://doi.org/10.1093/pastj/gty030]
-
Hunter, Ian. 2019. “The Contest over Context in Intellectual History.” History and Theory 58.2: 185–209.
[https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.12109]
-
James, Samuel. 2019. “J. G. A. Pocock and the Idea of the ‘Cambridge School’ in the History of Political Thought.” History of European Ideas 45.1: 83–98.
[https://doi.org/10.1080/01916599.2018.1498011]
-
Jay, Martin. 2011. “Historical Explanation and the Event: Reflections on the Limits of Contextualization.” New Literary History 42: 557–571.
[https://doi.org/10.1353/nlh.2011.0043]
- Kim, Youngmin. 2018. A History of Chinese Political Thought. Cambridge: Polity Press.
- Levenson, Joseph R. 1958. Confucian China and Its Modern Fate. The Problem of Intellectual Continuity. Vol. I. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
-
López, Rosario. 2016. “The Quest for the Global: Remapping Intellectual History.” History of European Ideas 42.1: 155–160.
[https://doi.org/10.1080/01916599.2015.1115250]
-
Lovejoy, Arthur O. 1941. “The Meaning of Romanticism for the Historian of Ideas.” Journal of the History of Ideas 11.3: 257–278.
[https://doi.org/10.2307/2707131]
-
Mandelbaum, Maurice. 1965. “The History of Ideas, Intellectual History, and the History of Philosophy.” History and Theory 5: 33–66.
[https://doi.org/10.2307/2504118]
- McMahon, Darrin M. 2006. Happiness: A History. New York: Grove Press.
-
McMahon, Darrin M. 2014. “The Return of the History of Ideas?” In Rethinking Modern European Intellectual History, edited by Darrin M. McMahon and Samuel Moyn, 13–31. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199769230.003.0001]
-
McMahon, Darrin M., and Samuel Moyn. 2014. “Introduction: Interim Intellectual History.” In Rethinking Modern European Intellectual History, edited by Darrin M. McMahon and Samuel Moyn, 3–12. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199769230.003.0000]
-
Moser, Jeffrey. 2012. “The Ethics of Immutable Things: Interpreting L Dalin’s Illustrated Investigations of Antiquity.” Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies 72.2: 259–293.
[https://doi.org/10.1353/jas.2012.0015]
-
Moyn, Samuel, and Andrew Sartori, eds. 2013. Global Intellectual History. New York: Columbia University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.7312/moyn16048]
-
Nelson, Eric. 2019. The Theology of Liberalism: Political Philosophy and the Justice of God. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.4159/9780674242944]
-
Pines, Yuri. 2009. Envisioning Eternal Empire: Chinese Political Thought of the Warring States Era. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.
[https://doi.org/10.21313/hawaii/9780824832759.001.0001]
-
Pines, Yuri. 2012. The Everlasting Empire: The Political Culture of Ancient China and Its Imperial Legacy. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.23943/princeton/9780691134956.001.0001]
-
Pocock, J. G. A. 2019. “On the Unglobality of Contexts: Cambridge Methods and the History of Political Thought.” Global Intellectual History 4.1: 1–14.
[https://doi.org/10.1080/23801883.2018.1523997]
- Qiao, Jiyan. 2020. “Human Nature and Governance—Political Theory in Eleventh Century China.” PhD diss., Leiden University.
-
Salkever, Stephen G., and Michael Nylan. 1994. “Comparative Political Philosophy and Liberal Education: ‘Looking for Friends in History.’” Political Science and Politics 27.2: 238–247.
[https://doi.org/10.2307/420279]
-
Sartori, Andrew. 2008. Bengal in Global Concept History: Culturalism in the Age of Capital. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.
[https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226734866.001.0001]
-
Skinner, Quentin. 1969. “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas.” History and Theory 8.1: 3–53.
[https://doi.org/10.2307/2504188]
-
Skinner, Quentin. 2001. “The Rise of, Challenge to and Prospects for a Collingwoodian Approach to the History of Political Thought.” In The History of Political Thought in National Context, edited by Dario Castiglione and Iain Hampsher-Monk, 175–188. Ideas in Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511521317.010]
-
Smith, Sophie. 2018. “Democracy and the Body Politic from Aristotle to Hobbes.” Political Theory 46.2: 167–196.
[https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591716649984]
-
Subrahmanyam, Sanjay. 2015. “Global Intellectual History beyond Hegel and Marx.” History and Theory 54.1: 126–137.
[https://doi.org/10.1111/hith.10746]
-
Symes, Carol. 2014. “Introducing the Medieval Globe.” The Medieval Globe 1.1: 1–8.
[https://doi.org/10.17302/TMG.1-1.1]
- Virág, Curie K. 2017. The Emotions in Early Chinese Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.